Monday, September 21, 2020

Lewis Namier by D.W. Hayton


 

There is no doubt that Namier was particularly doubtful of the value of ‘the liberal spirit’. His dislike of liberalism began in adolescence; imbibed, along with pan-Slavism, from listening to his tutors and reading Dostoyevsky. The great figures of the European liberal pantheon may have been his family’s household gods, but he saw them and their ideology  as gods who had failed the Slavs of central and eastern Europe, while German liberalism had proved unable to withstand the pathology of the German national character and had transmuted into the Prussianised nationalism that would reach its apogee under the Nazis. The First World War and its aftermath only confirmed his distrust of bien-pensant progressivism, exemplified in the League of Nations, which he despised in spite of the fact that [his friend] ‘Baffy’ Dugdale worked for it. The League was a creation of political ingenues, insulated from the realities of European politics, who believed they could ‘cure humanity and lead it into better ways. It was the expression of the morality and idealism of the Anglo-Saxons, and of their ignorance of what it means to suffer of neighbors and disputed borderlands.’ With his background, Namier understood that, as George Orwell observed, ‘nationalism, religious bigotry and loyalty are far more powerful forces than . . .sanity.’*

Namier was also impatient with silver-tongued orators like Charles James Fox, who clouded their sordid intentions with rhetorical vapor. Fox ‘talked in a grand manner’ and ostentatiously displayed ‘moral indignation . . .towards other people’ while leading a life of debauchery. The harm done by twentieth-century demagogues scarcely needs stating: ‘what shams and diseases political ideologies are apt to be, we surely have had an opportunity to learn.’ At the same time, Namier readily admitted the power of ideas to sway a parliamentary audience. The ‘independent country gentlemen’ of the eighteenth century had to be convinced by argument, and Namier fully appreciated that some politicians, of whom Pitt the elder was a classic example, owed their influence to the powers of persuasion rather than to battalions of parliamentary dependents.

Namier’s own biography, especially his early life, was marked by a personal commitment to ideals and ideologies: socialism, pan-Slavism, the libertarian constitutionalism inherited by Americans from seventeenth-century England, and eventually, and most enduringly, the precepts and aspirations of Zionism. How could such a man come to believe that ideas did not matter in politics, however skeptical he might be of liberal beliefs, and however much he disliked mountebanks who duped the public and their elected representatives with bogus appeals to principle?

The first thing to note is that Namier differentiated between levels of argument: between debates over specific problems, and what he would have considered the airy rehearsals of generalities. Under this latter heading would come high-flown discussions about constitutional practice in terms of prevailing notions of good government. Such commonplaces were generally innocuous, though they could be dangerous when exploited by those wishing to do mischief. This was the context of his notorious use of the term  ‘flapdoodle.’ Neither could he see the point of the historian spending time in examining closely the way such sentiments were expressed. They were merely the ‘current cant’ of politics; the only conceivable interest lay in examining their relationship to political reality.

In the same way that he was mystified by Butterfield’s interest in historiography- historians should study what happened in the past, not their predecessors’ generally mistaken notions of what happened – Namier was unable to see the point of what we now call ‘the history of ideas’. Or rather, he did not consider it to be the realm of the historian proper: the story of the development of political philosophy was best left to political philosophers like his friend Isaiah Berlin. **  Namier’s overly candid confession of his own inability to comprehend Berlin’s work was by no means disingenuous politeness, and although he was not the boor he claimed to be, he did not regard himself as an intellectual: ‘I am not good at abstract thought.’ When a BBC producer asked Namier to a series on the Third Programme and sent him a copy of one of the other talks, by the philosopher Stuart Hampshire on ‘Reason in politics’, he was nonplussed, describing Hampshire’s discourse as being ‘in the clouds’. He wondered whether, ‘if there is to be much of that kind in this series . . .you will want me as a bull in the china shop.’ Namier fully recognized the importance of ideas, especially in political life, but in a curious way as abstracted from human consciousness. In one late night conversation with Baffy Dugdale he talked of ‘the curious separate life which Idea develops’:

It has to be born in the brain of a man, but when it begins to grow in the minds of others, it becomes invested with qualities of its own, derived, of course, from them, but beyond the control of any one of them. They become in a way its servants, not its masters –must watch for its reactions, and in away obey them.

For Namier the subject-matter of history was ‘human affairs, men in action, things which have happened and how they happened; concrete events fixed in time and space, and their grounding in the thoughts and feelings of men. It was a view which became more deeply embedded the older he got, and the more enmeshed he became in the work of the History of Parliament. In his own work Namier encountered eighteenth-century constitutional principles primarily in the context of private correspondence, diaries, and memoirs, or parliamentary debates, as politicians justified their own actions, to themselves and each other, and sought to persuade MP’s to follow them. The contemporary pamphlets which he had studied so intensively in his first attempts at research were rarely cited in his two great books, and figured even more fleetingly in his History of Parliament. When he considered the expression of these grand ideas he concerned himself not with the ideas themselves but with the way in which they were being used. In examining any historical statement it was vital to take account of ‘context, emphasis and circumstances. Ideas were instrumental; they expressed and in some cases disguised motives rather than  constituting motives in themselves.

Character and motivation were what primarily interested Namier. His rejection of principle was not, as it has often been described, mere cynicism. The analysis was deeper and more systematic. By the time of his maturity he had cast aside is juvenile belief in a crude economic determinism, whether advocated by Marx or Chares Beard. Reports that he had once been influenced by Marx could be guaranteed to infuriate him. Nonetheless, while he was able to recognize relatively early in life that human beings were perfectly capable of thinking and acting against their self-interest, he retained a vestigial deference towards calculations of motive based on economic circumstances.

The other great influence on the young Namier was Freud, and this he never discarded. When reading eighteenth-century letters he always paid close attention to uses of language that were ‘psychologically’ or ‘psych-analytically’ significant.  His character sketches of the leading characters in the political conflicts of the 1760s were heavily informed by Freudian psychology, always focusing on the gravitational effect of family and childhood experience. The Freudianism was quite explicit: Namier thought that the Duke of Newcastle suffered from ‘obsessional neurosis, and made a similar ‘diagnosis’ of George III. These refreshingly modern commentaries doubtless formed part of the book’s attractiveness when it first appeared. At the time Namier was still being psycho-analyzed himself, and although he stopped attending sessions when he married Julia, he did not relinquish his belief in the importance of thee workings of the subconscious, and in particular on the powerful and enduring impact of a tortured upbringing, to which he gave full rein in his public lectures on George III and Charles Townshend. ‘History has . . . a psycho-analytic function,’ he wrote in an essay in 1952, adding sharply that ‘it further resembles psycho-analysis in being better able to diagnose than to cure.’




*‘The energy that actually shapes the world springs from emotions – racial pride, leader-worship, religious belief, love f war – which liberal intellectuals mechanically write off as anachronisms, and which they have usually destroyed so completely in themselves as to have lost all power of action… [‘Wells, Hitler and the World State’, Horizon, August 1941]

**’In all sincerity I admire you: how intelligent you must be to understand all you write” he once wrote Berlin.



No comments:

Post a Comment