Glossary of Technical
Terms
Ochlos
Ranciere uses this Greek term meaning ‘ a throng of people’
or ‘multitude’ to refer to a community obsessed with its own unification, at
the expense of excluding the demos.
Demos
Ranciere uses this Greek term – meaning ‘the commons’, ‘plebians’,
or ‘citizens’ – interchangeably with ‘the people’
to refer to those who have no share in the communal distribution of the sensible. The demos is thus simultaneously the
name of the community and the title signifying the division of the community
due to a wrong. It is the unique power
of assembling and dividing that exceeds all of the arrangements made by
legislators; it is the force of communal division that contravenes the ochlos obsession with unification.
Subjectification
A process by which a
political subject extracts itself from the dominant categories of
identification and classification
Consensus
Prior to being a platform for rational debate, consensus is
a specific regime of the sensible, a particular way of positing rights as a
community’s arche [power, command, realm, empire]. More specifically,
consensus is the presupposition according to which every part of the population,
along with all its specific problems, can be incorporated into a political
order and taken into account. By abolishing dissensus and placing a ban on political subjectivization, consensus reduces politics to the police.
Dissensus
Dissensus is not
a quarrel over personal interests or opinions. It is a political process that
resists juridical litigation and creates a fissure in the sensible order by
confronting the established framework of perception, thought, and action with
the ‘inadmissible”, i.e. a political subject.
Democracy
Neither a form of government nor a style of social life,
democracy is properly speaking an act of political subjectivization that disturbs the police order by polemically
calling into question the aesthetic coordinates of perception, thought and
action. Democracy is thus falsely identified when it is associated with the
consensual self-regulation of the multitude or with the reign of a sovereign
collectivity based on subordinating the particular to the universal. It is,. In
fact, less a state of being than an act of contention that implements various
forms of dissensus. It can be said
to exist only when those who have no title to power, the demos, intervene as
the dividing force that disrupts the ochlos.
If a community can be referred to as democratic, it is only insofar as it is a ‘community
of sharing in which membership in a common world –not to be confused with a
communitarian social formation – is expressed in adversarial terms and
coalition only occurs in conflict.
Gabriel Rockhill: You have convincingly argued that theory and
practice are closely intertwined in the recent history of arts. Your own
theoretical practice is one that attempts to intervene in the consensual
systems in order to displace them, whether or not it be the discourse on artistic
modernity, the discourse on the avant-garde or other such examples. Could you
discuss the nature of your theoretical practice as a polemical intervention?
Are there aesthetic practices that try to do something along the lines of what you
do at a theoretical level, i.e. intervene in order to displace the consensual
framework of the sensible?
Jacques Ranciere: What I try to do is intervene in the space
connecting what is called aesthetics and what is called politics in order to
question forms of description that have supposedly become self-evident. For
instance, this is why both in what is supposed to be a political
book like Hatred of Democracy and what is supposed to be an aesthetic book, The Emancipated Spectator, I targeted more
or less the same discourse, which is very powerful on both sides: the discourse
on the spectacle and the idea that we are all enclosed in the field of the
commodity, the spectator, advertising images and so on. This is because, on the
one hand, this discourse generates a kind of anti-democratic discourse and the incapacity
of the masses for any political intervention and, on the other hand, it
nurtures a discourse on the uselessness of any kind of artistic practice because
it says everything depends on the market. For example, there were all these
reactions when I did an interview with Art
Forum: ‘ But there is the market, and it’s true that the market. . .’
But it’s necessary to get out of this discourse, which is the discourse of
impotence, which nurtures, at the same time, forms of art that are supposed to
be critical, projects and installations that are supposed to make us discover
the power of the commodity and the spectacle. This is something that nobody
ignores anymore. This discourse generates a kind of stereotypical art with all
these installations presenting displays of commodities, all these displays of
images of sex or gender identity, etc. So what I try to do is really target
certain topics that both create some kind of discourse of political impotence
and, on the other hand, either generate an idea that art cannot do anything or
what you have to do is reproduce the stereotypical criticism of the commodity and
consumption.
Alexi Kukuljevic: These stereotypical responses within the art
world could perhaps be identified as avant-gardist or neo-avant-guardist
attempts to critically respond to something like the spectacle of culture. You
seem to be suggesting that there is a type of critical art that is more
productive as an intervention or as a critique of contemporary society, a
critical art that avoids the more stereotypical types of art that remain
ensnared or entrapped in the logic of consumerist spectacle. Given your
critique of modernism in the attempt to reopen the question of the aesthetic
outside of the avant-gardist paradigm, how do you at the same time identify
certain normative critical structures within the arts? Is there ultimately a
normative aspect to your discourse?
Jacques Ranciere:
I think that the critical spectacle has nothing to do with the avant-garde
tradition because the avant-garde tradition is a tradition of art creating forms
of life, and not art as a criticism of social stereotypes. I think that political
art is itself something of a kind of leftover from the real political
avant-garde tradition. This being said , I don’t have a fixed idea of some
normative form of critique. What I mean is that I don’t think that there are
normative forms so that you could just refer to them and establish a way of doing
real political art. I just observe forms of displacement, breaking in some respects
with the consensual way in which things are presented, told and made in the
mainstream system. There are many examples . . .I have discussed, for instance,
the way in which Alfredo Jaar dealt with the massacre in Rwanda and how he escaped the discourse of the
unrepresentable. He doesn’t show images of the slaughter, but he created an
installation in which what he makes visible is the look of people or imply
their identity. For instance there is an installation with black boxes where
images were hidden in the boxes, but there were descriptions of the contents of
the images on the boxes. There was thus an identification of the person, which
means that he emphasized the fact that all those people have names and a place
in history, whereas usually the victim is the one who has no names and no
individuality (only an image as the victim of the slaughter). He breaks, in
this case, with the partition between the part of the world that is constituted
by individuals and the part of the world that is constituted by anonymous
masses. However, I am not presenting a normative idea of what art has to do. I
really don’t think that there is a good practice of art. The relation between
the consensual image and subversive images is constantly shifting so that you
have to, each moment, displace the displacement itself.
As a matter of fact, political art cannot work in the simple
form of a meaningful spectacle that would lead to an ‘’awareness’ of the state
of the world. Suitable political art would ensure, at one in the same time, the
production of a double effect: the readability of a political of a political
signification and a sensible or perceptual shock caused, conversely, by the
uncanny, by that which resists signification. In fact, this ideal effect is
always the object of negotiation between opposites, between the readability of
the message that threatens to destroy the sensible form of art and the radical
uncanniness that threatens to destroy all political meaning.
What is important is not that a work can have this or that
effect. The effect, the aesthetic effect, is not the effect of a work in the sense that a work should
produce this energy for action or this particular form of deliberation about a
situation. It’s about creating forms of perception, forms on interpretation-
not all of which the artist can anticipate. The role of the critic – which is a
controversial name for me – is to draw the outlines of the kind of world of
which the work is a product. For me, the role of the critic is to say, ‘this is
the world that this work proposes.’ It is to try to explain the forms – as well
as possible shifts in the forms – of perception, description and interpretation
of a world that are inherent in the work.
No comments:
Post a Comment